Barak’s RuleReviewed by Robert H. BorkThe Judge in a Democracy by Aharon Barak Princeton University Press, 2006, 360 pages Despite this, Barak is at pains to assure us that “It is not his own subjective values that the judge imposes on the society in which he operates.” Rather, he must balance various conflicting interests objectively and come to a conclusion. “The question is not what the judge wants but what society needs.” Since voiding a statute requires overriding the will of the people as expressed through their elected representatives, what a judge thinks “society needs” is almost certainly what a majority of the people in that society do not want. It is, in any event, incorrect to suppose that a society’s “need” is a fact that can be determined by an objective balancing of interests. In truth, the most important interests are likely to be conflicting value judgments. How, for instance, does a judge know whether a society “needs” freedom of abortion, some degree of regulation, or a prohibition of abortion altogether? How can a judge determine whether his or her society “needs” a constitutional right to homosexual marriage? How does he decide “objectively” whether religious education in state-supported schools should be required, made optional, or prohibited? The answer, of course, is that the judge does not, and cannot, “know” any of these things, though he may have strong feelings about them. Because the judge is, by definition, operating without guidance from positive law, it is almost certain that his personal opinions will turn out to be what society “needs.” Though Barak would deny it, The Judge in a Democracy is a textbook for judicial activists. I have written that a judge is an activist if he reaches results or announces principles that cannot plausibly be derived from the constitution he cites. Here Barak responds that my “description is not of an activist judge but rather of a judge who is not worthy of the position he occupies.” I agree that such a man is unworthy to be a judge, but he is unworthy precisely because he is an activist. I do not see how a judge can, in accordance with Barak’s philosophy, change the meaning of a statute without changing its words, or introduce new fundamental principles into a constitution without being either an activist in my terms, or unworthy in Barak’s. Barak goes on to say that “None of us may turn our personal beliefs into the law of the land.” But I think it is clear that the judge who follows Barak’s prescriptions cannot avoid legislating, and it is highly unlikely that he will legislate beliefs other than his own. Indeed, Barak’s impatience with originalism demonstrates that his philosophy is, in fact, activist. “Why can some enlightened democratic legal systems (such as those of Canada, Australia, and Germany) extricate themselves from the heavy hands of intentionalism and originalism in interpreting the constitution,” he asks, “while constitutional law in the United States remains mired in these difficulties?” Originalism simply means that judges must attempt to apply the principles of the constitution as they were understood by the men who made the constitution law. When a judge departs from originalism, he necessarily legislates; he lays down law that the constitution does not contain. Judges like Barak and his counterparts in the It is true that Israeli, Canadian, and many American judges have extricated themselves from originalism, and the result has been overweening judicial branches. I count it as a virtue that the By contrast, built into Barak’s jurisprudence are so many ways to arrive at any conclusion judges like that there is not space to analyze them all here. The actual decisions of the court demonstrate what Barak’s free-wheeling approach means in practice. The results range from ludicrous to officious to dangerous. To wit: 1. The Knesset legislated local authority to limit or forbid the sale of pork. But President Barak and eight other justices held that there is a constitutional right not only to eat pork, but also to obtain one’s pork without inconvenience. Thus, in an impressive show of disregard for a piece of Knesset legislation, the court ruled that a locality wishing to ban the sale of pork must examine the availability of stores selling pork nearby, the means of transportation to those stores, and the practicability of using that transportation. Only, they concluded, if this examination reveals that the alternatives are feasible may pork sales indeed be banned in a given locality. 2. The court decided that it has the authority to rule on whether welfare cuts are constitutional, effectively creating a constitutional right to a minimum income to be determined by the court—a decision that flew in the face of the manifest will of the Knesset that no such right does or should exist. Thus has the court assumed the power to tell the elected branches on what they must spend, and how much, establishing the principle that, in fact, it is judges, and not legislators, who ultimately control 3. A majority of the court held that the government cannot bar immigration from hostile areas during wartime because doing so would infringe on the right of Israeli Arabs to marry Palestinians and to bring them into 4. While upholding the government’s authority to build a separation fence, the court nevertheless overruled the army’s judgment on the purely military issue of the location of parts of the fence, because of disagreement about the minimally adequate level of security. Barak once said that the court has jurisdiction to judge the deployment of troops in wartime; this decision brings it closer to that. 5. The court ruled that a government official could be discharged or denied promotion on the basis of what he said during a published interview. Indeed, the court itself proposed to investigate whether the official’s words rendered him unfit for appointment. Without any legislative mandate or guidance—and in stunning defiance of the fundamental democratic principle of free speech—the court thus determined to make the law as to an appointee’s moral character. This unprecedented role as censor is simply unknown in other democracies. 6. Faced with a possible reform of immigration policy by the Knesset’s adoption of a new Basic Law on the subject, President Barak wrote in an opinion that the court had the authority to invalidate a Basic Law if the justices thought it contrary to In a word, Barak’s court can turn ordinary legislation into a constitution, force it on the nation, and then announce that it can prevent any democratic amendment. In this, Barak surely establishes a world record for judicial hubris. As these and other cases demonstrate, it would appear that Barak is unconcerned that the rule of law—which he praises as part of “substantive democracy”—is in fact being replaced by the rule of judges, a trend to which he himself is the major contributor. Perhaps he believes that judges are simply intellectually and morally superior to other actors in the nation’s politics, and thus judicial authoritarianism is necessary. As he explains, “a branch of government should not judge itself. It is therefore appropriate that the final decision about the legality of the activities of the legislative and executive branches should be taken by a mechanism external to those branches, that is, the judiciary.” Yet the judicial branch is properly subject to no such external mechanism, “because of their [the judges’] education, profession, and role,” and because they are “trained and accustomed to dealing with conflicts of interest.” Judges may be trusted, moreover, since they are “not fighting for their own power.” Surely anyone familiar with Barak’s record will see the irony in that statement. Alexander Hamilton, in Federalist 78, wrote that “the judiciary, from the nature of its functions, will always be the least dangerous to the political rights of the Constitution,” because it “has no influence over either the sword or the purse.” |
From the
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |